%! TEX root = FC.tex % vim: tw=50 % 25/01/2025 12PM \newpage \section{The Continuum Hypothesis} 1398: G\"odel showed $\Con(\ZFC) \implies \Con(\ZFC + \CH)$. 1962: Cohen showed $\Con(\ZFC) \implies \Con(\ZFC + \neg\CH)$. \begin{theorem*}[Hartogs's Theorem] For every set $X$, there is a (least) cardinal $\alpha$ such that there is no injection from $\alpha$ to $X$. \end{theorem*} We denote this by Hartogs's aleph of $X$, $\aleph(X)$. \begin{theorem*} For every set $X$, there is no injection from $\mathcal{P}(X)$ into $X$. We denote this by $2^{|X|}$. \end{theorem*} Using Axiom of Choice, well-order $\mathcal{P}(X)$ and get ordinal $2^{|X|}$. We have \[ \aleph(X) \le 2^{|X|} .\] \begin{notation*} Define: \begin{align*} \aleph_0 &\defeq \Nbb \\ \aleph_{\alpha + 1} &\defeq \aleph(\aleph_\alpha) \\ \aleph_\lambda &\defeq \bigcup_{\alpha < \lambda} \aleph_\alpha \\ \beth_0 &= \Nbb \\ \beth_{\alpha + 1} &= 2^{\beth_\alpha} \\ \beth_\lambda &= \bigcup_{\alpha < \lambda} \beth_\alpha \end{align*} Clearly, $\aleph_\alpha \le \beth_\alpha$. \end{notation*} Continuum Hypothesis (CH): $\aleph_1 = \beth_1$. Generalised Continuum Hypothesis (GCH): $\forall \alpha \aleph_\alpha = \beth_\alpha$. Why ``continuum''? \begin{lemma*} \begin{iffc} \lhs CH \rhs $\forall X \subseteq \Rbb$, $X$ is uncountable $\implies$ $X \sim \Rbb$ ($\sim$ means ``there is a bijection''). \end{iffc} \end{lemma*} \begin{iffproof} \rightimpl Obvious since $\beth_1 = |\Rbb|$. \leftimpl Suppose $|\Rbb| > \aleph_1$. Well-order the reals in order type $\kappa > \aleph_1$: \[ \{r_\alpha : \alpha < \kappa\} .\] Consider $X \defeq \{r_\alpha : \alpha < w_1\} \subseteq \Rbb$. This is a subset of the reals of cardinality $\aleph_1$, hence is an uncountable subset which is not in bijection with it. \end{iffproof} Reminder: G\"odel showed $\Con(\ZFC) \implies \Con(\ZFC + \CH)$. Cohen showed $\Con(\ZFC) \implies \Con(\ZFC + \neg\CH)$. Relative consistency proofs. By Completeness Theorem, this means: If there is $M \models \ZFC$, then I can construct $N \models \ZFC + (\neg) \CH$. Analogy from algebra: \[ \mathcal{L}_{\text{fields}} = \{0, 1, +, \cdot, -, {}^{-1}\} .\] Axioms of fields: Fields. Let $\varphi_{\sqrt{2}} \defeq \exists x (x \cdot x = 1 + 1)$. Note $\Qbb \models \neg \varphi_{\sqrt{2}}$. \textbf{Idea:} Start with $\Qbb$ and extend $\Qbb$ to get $F \models \text{Fields} + \varphi_{\sqrt{2}}$. Construct by \emph{algebraic closure} (not in the usual sense -- here we just mean adding in $\sqrt{2}$ and then adding everything else that this requires us to add). Obtain $\Qbb(\sqrt{2}) \models \text{Fields} + \varphi_{\sqrt{2}}$. This is easy because everything that matters (Fields and $\varphi_{\sqrt{2}}$) is determined by equations; all formulas we need to check are atomic. \begin{fcdefn}[absolute] \glsadjdefn{abs}{absolute}{formula}% \glsadjdefn{uabs}{upwards absolute}{formula}% \glsadjdefn{dabs}{downwards absolute}{formula}% If $M \subseteq N$ and $M, N$ are $\mathcal{L}$-structures and $\varphi$ an $\mathcal{L}$-formula, then we say \emph{$\varphi$ is absolute between $M$ and $N$} if for all $x_1, \ldots, x_m \in M$, \[ M \models \varphi(x_1, \ldots, x_n) \iff N \models \varphi(x_1, \ldots, x_n) .\] If the $\Rightarrow$ direction holds, then we say ``upwards absolute'', and if the $\Leftarrow$ direction holds, then we say ``downwards absolute''. \end{fcdefn} \begin{theorem*}[Substructure Lemma] All atomic formulas are \gls{abs} between substructures. \end{theorem*} WHat if we have models of ZFC? Have \[ \mathcal{L}_\in = \{\in\} .\] No function symbols nor constant symbols. So: almost nothing is atomic. $M \subseteq N$ if and only if $M$ is an $\mathcal{L}_\in$-substructure of $N$. And: the formulas that we care about are definitely not atomic, but instead very complex. Try to imagine a proof of: If $M \models \ZFC$ then there is $N \supseteq M$ such that $N \models \ZFC + \CH$. Without loss of generality $M \models \neg \CH$ (else we are done). For simplicity, let's consider the case $\beth_1 = \aleph_2$. \begin{center} \includegraphics[width=0.1\linewidth]{images/1c3d0e1625ef4d79.png} \end{center} What can we do to ``get rid of $\aleph_1$''? Maybe a surjection $f : \Nbb \to \aleph_1$. Maybe we can form $M[f] \supseteq M$ to get a smallest model $M[f] \models \ZFC$. Clearly, in $M[f]$, $\aleph_1^M$ is not a cardinal anymore. Does that show CH? All sorts of things can happen Assuming it is actually possible to form this smallest model $M[f]$, there are lots of ways that this might not end up being enough to deduce CH. For example: \begin{itemize} \item Maybe $\Rbb^{M[f]} \neq \Rbb^M$ \item Maybe $\aleph_2^M$ is not a cardinal either \end{itemize} \subsubsection*{A fundamental problem of non-absoluteness} Consider $\varphi_\emptyset(x) \defeq \forall z(z \notin x)$, which means ``$x$ is empty''. Consider $M \models \ZFC$. Therefore there are $e, e'$ such that $M \models \varphi_\emptyset(e)$ and $M \models \forall z(z \in e' \iff z = e)$. Consider $N \defeq M \setminus \{e\}$. $N$ is an $\mathcal{L}_\in$-substructure of $M$. But $N \models \varphi_\emptyset(e')$, even though $M \models \neg \varphi_\emptyset(e')$. So $\varphi_\emptyset$ is not \gls{abs} between substructures. Instead of substructures, we will restrict out attention to \emph{transitive substructures}: in particular, to $M$ transitive ($\forall x, x \in M \implies x \subseteq M$ or equivalently $x \in M \wedge y \in x \implies y \in M$) such that $M \models \ZFC$. Next time: theorems about absoluteness for transitive substructures.